Euclidean geometry

From Example Problems
Jump to: navigation, search
For a topic other than geometry whose name includes the word "Euclidean", see Euclidean algorithm.

In mathematics, Euclidean geometry is the familiar kind of geometry on the plane or in three dimensions. Mathematicians sometimes use the term to encompass higher dimensional geometries with similar properties.

It is important to remember that, in the original and correct conception, geometry is, first of all, a physical science ("the noblest of the physical sciences"); that is, the logical definition of geometry (its fundamental assumptions or axioms) arises directly out of observation. Abstract geometries may be exclusively mathematical, but, whenever so, they are different from physical geometries.

Euclidean geometry sometimes means geometry in the plane which is also called plane geometry. Plane geometry is the topic of this article. Euclidean geometry is also based off of the Point-Line-Plane postulate. Euclidean geometry in three dimensions is traditionally called solid geometry. For information on higher dimensions see Euclidean space.

Plane geometry is the kind of geometry usually taught in secondary school. Euclidean geometry is named after the Greek mathematician Euclid. Euclid's text Elements is an early systematic treatment of this kind of geometry.

Axiomatic approach

The traditional presentation of Euclidean geometry is as an axiomatic system, setting out to prove all the "true statements" as theorems in geometry from a set of finite number of axioms.

The five postulates of the Elements are:

  1. Any two points can be joined by a straight line.
  2. Any straight line segment can be extended indefinitely in a straight line.
  3. Given any straight line segment, a circle can be drawn having the segment as radius and one endpoint as center.
  4. All right angles are congruent.
  5. If two lines are drawn which intersect a third in such a way that the sum of the inner angles on one side is less than two right angles, then the two lines inevitably must intersect each other on that side if extended far enough.

The fifth postulate is called the parallel postulate, which leads to the same geometry as the following statement (note that it is formulated for two-dimensional geometry):

Through a point not on a given straight line, one and only one line can be drawn that never meets the given line.

The parallel postulate seems less obvious than the others and many geometers tried in vain to prove it from them. By 1763 at least 28 different proofs of the fifth postulate had been published, but all were found to be incorrect. [1] In the 19th century it was shown that this could not be done, by constructing hyperbolic geometry where the parallel postulate is false, while the other axioms hold. (If one simply drops the parallel postulate from the list of axioms then the result is the more general geometry called absolute geometry).

Interestingly one of the results of the fifth Euclidean axiom being a non-logical axiom is that the three angles of a triangle do not by definition add to 180°. In Hyperbolic geometry the sum of the three angles are always less than 180 and can approach zero. Only under the umbrella of Euclidean geometry are then angles always portions of 180°.

Another thing that was observed was that Euclid's five axioms are actually somewhat incomplete. For instance, one of his theorems is that any line segment is part of a triangle; he constructs this in the usual way, by drawing circles around both endpoints and taking their intersection as third vertex. His axioms, however, do not guarantee that the circles actually intersect.

Many revised systems of axioms were constructed, the most standard ones are Hilbert's axioms, Birkhoff's axioms, and Tarski's axioms. Tarski used his axioms to show Euclidean geometry is a complete decidable theory; that is, every proposition of Euclidean geometry can be shown to be either true or false.

Euclid also had five "common notions" which can also be taken to be axioms, though he later used other properties of magnitudes.

  1. Things which equal the same thing also equal one another.
  2. If equals are added to equals, then the wholes are equal.
  3. If equals are subtracted from equals, then the remainders are equal.
  4. Things which coincide with one another equal one another.
  5. The whole is greater than the part.

Modern introduction to Euclidean geometry

Today, Euclidean geometry is usually constructed rather than axiomatized, by means of analytic geometry. If one introduces geometry this way, one can then prove the Euclidean (or any other) axioms as theorems in this particular model. This does not have the beauty of the axiomatic approach, but it is extremely concise.

The construction

First let us define the set of points as set of pairs of real numbers (x,y). Then given two points P=(x,y) and Q=(z,t) one can define distances using the following formula:

|PQ|={\sqrt  {(x-z)^{2}+(y-t)^{2}}}.

This is known as the Euclidean metric. All other notions as a straight line, angle, circle can be defined in terms of points as pairs of real numbers and the distances between them. For example straight line through P and Q can be defined as a set of points A such that the triangle APQ is degenerate, i.e.

|PQ|=|PA|+|AQ|{\mbox{ or }}|PQ|=\pm (|PA|-|AQ|).

References

Classical theorems

See also

External links

da:Euklidisk geometri de:Euklidische Geometrie el:Ευκλείδεια Γεωμετρία fa:هندسه‌ اقليدسی fr:Géométrie euclidienne ko:유클리드 기하학 io:Euklidana spaco it:Geometria euclidea he:גאומטריה אוקלידית nl:Postulaten van Euclides ja:ユークリッド幾何学 pt:Geometria euclidiana ro:Geometrie euclediană sv:Euklidisk geometri tr:Öklid geometrisi zh:欧几里德几何